Thứ Ba, 1 tháng 1, 2019

Auto news on Youtube Jan 1 2019

This is how Quran defines the names of Allah

هُوَ اللَّهُ الَّذِي لَا إِلَٰهَ إِلَّا هُوَ الْمَلِكُ الْقُدُّوسُ السَّلَامُ الْمُؤْمِنُ الْمُهَيْمِنُ الْعَزِيزُ الْجَبَّارُ الْمُتَكَبِّرُ ۚ سُبْحَانَ اللَّهِ عَمَّا يُشْرِكُونَ

"He is Allah , other than whom there is no deity, the Sovereign.."

This is what our brothers and sisters need to understand the most.

When it comes to worship in this world, then it ONLY belongs to Allah

Including bowing, prostrating, seeking help, seeking refuge, seeking forgiveness etc.

This is only ordained for Allah which Allah has fixed to Himself.

Therefore, DO NOT do any act of obedience to someone which is only ordained for Allah

E.g. worshiping or praying to someone alongside with Allah, or calling for help..

This is what SHIRK is!

Regardless of whatever mighty status that person has. The act of worship is only to be done for Allah.

We are taught to recite the Kalimah, the creed of Islam, the Shahadah in our childhood which reads:

لا الہ الا اللہ محمد رسول اللہ There's no deity except for Allah Muhammad is the messenger of Allah

Meaning in the WHOLE universe there can never be a single diety who should be worshiped.

A Phoroah, An Emperor, A King or EVEN if He is a Prophet of God. He can never be worshiped.

Only ALLAH deserves worship!

..and if someone mistakenly associates any parter with God, bowing down to a temple or shrine ...

..then no doubt he or she has also called a sanction of God upon him or herself.

Allah has clearly said, he can forgive ANY sin except for Shirk.

Therefore, if a human being regardless of what religion they belong to should keep it in their minds..

.. then never should he or she do an act of worship to someone else other then the ONLY true un-seen God.

For more infomation >> Bollywood Actor Qadir / Kader Khan explains Shirk - What is Shirk? [URDU] - Duration: 2:20.

-------------------------------------------

What is he saying?(98) (Listening Practice) [ ForB English Lesson ] - Duration: 2:25.

Hello everyone and welcome back to ForB's English lesson video.

My name is Richard and today, I'm going to say something three times quickly

and I'd like you to guess what I'm saying.

Are you ready?

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

Did you catch it?

Alright, let's try that again, but this time with hint.

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

Did you catch it?

Alright, let's try it again but this time a little bit slower.

Are you ready?

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

Did you catch it?

Alright, the answer is "The event was called off."

The event was called off.

Alright, so in the word 'event' the 't' has a soft sound.

So it sounds almost, like it's not there.

The event was.

The event was.

And 'called off' is combined, so together it sounds like 'calledoff', 'calledoff'.

Alright, 'called off' means cancelled.

So in this case, the event was cancelled.

Alright, let's practice that together.

First slowly, then a little bit faster after that.

Please repeat after me.

The event was called off.

Great, now a little bit faster after that.

The event was called off.

Great, now even faster.

The event was called off.

Great, now let's try that three times quickly.

So, please repeat after me.

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

The event was called off.

Great, so now you know how to pronounce this expression.

My name is Richard.

Remember to please click like, share, and subscribe and I'll catch you next time.

For more infomation >> What is he saying?(98) (Listening Practice) [ ForB English Lesson ] - Duration: 2:25.

-------------------------------------------

Why is communication important in business? | Express Gut Instincts - Duration: 1:18.

Hey guys! I appreciate you tuning in for this episode of The Mental Minute. Today,

I'm going to be talking about communication, and the best way that you can

get the information that's up here, coordinate it with your gut, and then

externalize that. You know, when I was having a lot of issues processing things,

I realized that I had a lot of information up here, but I just didn't

know how to express it. And the problem that I had is that anytime that I

would have some sort of communication with somebody, generally, I would always

fill in the blanks because I thought it was just an excellent opportunity for me

to get out what was up here and externalize it. However, I realized that

was actually the wrong thing to do it. So, here's a tip on how you can improve your

communication with somebody: only respond to questions being asked. Don't respond

to statements, don't respond to basically anything where you interject any sort of

opinions unless asked. The reason that you do that is if somebody

wants to know something from you, eventually, they're going to ask. The

problems that you may have is that when you attempt to fill in the blanks and

give information, it's not necessarily what the other person is thinking.

For more infomation >> Why is communication important in business? | Express Gut Instincts - Duration: 1:18.

-------------------------------------------

What If Rodan Was Real? - Duration: 7:10.

Any of you guys scared of birds?

Granted - they're frantic and they've got beady eyes, but - not so much scary as

they are annoying.

Well, how about a bird the size of a skyscraper - that's also a prehistoric atomic monster

bird, capable of achieving supersonic flight and leveling cities with a flap of its wings.

Scared now?

Well - don't worry, because all it wants to do is settle down on it's own private

island and be at peace.

Maybe.

Hopefully - fingers crossed.

Hello internet - and welcome back to the most inquisitive channel on YouTube - Life's

Biggest Questions.

As always - I'll be your disembodied floating voice Jack Finch - and today, we're sliding

back into the chaotic world of the kaiju - and quizzically asking the question - What If

Rodan Was Real?

Roll the clip.

Now - here at LBQ - you know for a fact that we love a hypothetical kaiju monster battle

showdown - most of which often end in the levelling of a few cities, underwater cataclysmic

events - hellfire, or a destructive combination of the three.

But what if it didn't have to be that way?

What if our planet was held under the sway and influence of a gigantic, all powerful

- yet brave and loyal monster?

What if somewhere - tucked away in a remote pacific archipelago of islands - was a creature

that would fight tooth and nail in the defense of civilization.

Alright - perhaps not because it wanted to - but, well - when you're a big, prehistoric

atomic monster bird - there's not much else to do.

Before we soar into those Rodan wrought skies though folks - you know the drill by now.

If you're a fan of this video, the Kaiju - Godzilla, Mothra, King Ghidorah, Rodan - or

any of their equally terrifying best friends - then please, be a dear and make sure you

hit that thumbs up button - as well as that subscribe bell, so you can stay up to date

with our latest and greatest uploads.

Also - we'd just like to extend our absolutely mammoth thanks to all of our subscribers - old

and new - we couldn't have hit a milly without you all, so cheers for sticking around.

Double also - make sure to hang about all the way to the end of this video - where we'll

be reading out some of your more humorous comments from the past few days.

Alright - let's lay down the groundwork.

Also known as Monster Zero-Two, Fire Rodan, The Atomic Monster Bird - and The One Born

of Fire.

In Japanese, this guys name is actually Radon - being a contraction of pteranodon - and

being a linguistic nod to the radioactive origins of the Kaiju.

In North America though - it's Rodan - because, eh - why not.

Measuring in between a staggering 50 to 100 metres, and weighing in at between 15 thousand

and 30 thousand metric tonnes - it's safe to say that Rodan is a pretty thicc boi.

But it's not really his stature that we're concerned about - because as this Kaiju has

demonstrated time and time again, he's pretty well seasoned with the old knocking buildings

over and smashing fighter jets out of the sky with a slap of the wing.

Rodan's most noticeable trait is his legendary flying speed - which allows him to effortlessly

outmaneuver and outrun supersonic jets.

Put it this way - the fastest flight air speed ever achieved on record was the Lockheed SR-71

Blackbird back in 1976 which clocked in at a staggering 2193 miles per hour.

Yeah - that's a walk in the park for the Atomic Monster Bird - or, well - a flap in

the park, I guess?

Since then - most of our advancements have been in surface to atmosphere hypersonic jet

flight, but come on - you're not going to be chasing Rodan around the planet in a SpaceX

Falcon-9 rocket - you need something that can at least do a stylish barrel roll.

But that's by the by really - because what would be the point in trying to take Rodan

down?

As we known from the Kaiju's Showa series - that's never really ended well.

In his cinematic debut - in the 1956 tokusatsu kaiju film - even the trailer makes it very

plain and simple.

Supersonic jets cannot catch him!

Rockets cannot stop him!

Armored tanks are helpless before him!

Even guided missiles are powerless!

Well - yeah, that's a lot of resources to be spending - and if we know anything from

the events of the 1956 film, we know that even destroying him and his girlfriend in

a volcano only serves to annoy him - and extend his reign of beastial destruction for a few

more years.

Because here's the point - we wouldn't want to be enemies with Rodan - we'd want

to be his friend - and when you boil it all down, he's a pretty simple guy to get to

know.

It was during the events of the 1964 movie Ghidorah, the Three Headed Monster - that

Rodan began to show his true colours.

Throughout the film, the evil cosmic villain King Ghidorah reigns death and destruction

on planet Earth - and the only kaiju willing to defend humanity is the serene and powerful

Mothra - who is no match for King Ghidorah alone - but knows that if herself, Godzilla

and Rodan team up for the sake of mankind - they can take down King Ghidorah and the

planet will be saved.

Thankfully - Mothra convinces Rodan and Godzilla that humanity is worth saving and that Earth

belongs to all creatures equally - and the trifecta of noble kaiju save the day.

If Rodan was real - our best bet would to be the best global roommate we could hope

to be.

We'd literally have a sentient space-dragon who's only need and desire is to chill out

on a remote pacific island - sipping cocktails, probably, or something.

Humanity should be scrambling to make the Atomic Monster Bird as comfortable as they

could make him.

Global summits should be held on how we could best appease our winged neighbour.

We should get to know him as best as we can, and hope to high heaven that he sticks around.

Because here's the crux of the whole scenario - humans, if anything, are really- really

good at killing things.

Rodan would cause a lot of destruction if he was our enemy - he'd for sure wipe a

few cities off the map with ease.

But eventually, inevitably we'd find a way to destroy him.

BUT - and it's a very big BUT - why would we ever want to throw away the hypothetical

chance at having a true, planetary defender and a guardian of our skies - because, heck

- when the alien invasion rolls around, we'll all be hoping we had a few kaiju to save the

day.

Well - there we have it folks.

How do you think events would play out if Rodan or the rest of the kaiju were real?

Let us know your thoughts in the comment box below.

Before we depart, let's take a look at some of your more creative comments from the past

few days.

First off - Lord Petar says - what if jack finch didn't exist - and, well Lord Petar

- I'd love to answer that question fully but your profile picture is Teemo - and that

tells me that you're a whole different kind of evil.

Sorry buddy, I'm not overextending into that mushroom patch.

-- In regard to our What If The Sun Was Green video - Dirtneck Gaming says - What movie

was that clip from?

Well friend, that clip was from Danny Boyle's awesome 2007 film - Sunshine.

We just - err - well we turned it green.

If you haven't seen it, check it out - it's not in green though so don't worry.

-- Sandra Deras says - what's inquisitive!!? - well Sandra, the word inquisitive is defined

as someone eager to acquire knowledge - or better described as curious.

I hope that clears things up for you.

Thanks for sticking around all the way to the end questioneers - don't forget to hit

that thumbs up button - and we'll be seeing you in the next one.

As per usual, I've been your disembodied floating voice Jack Finch - you've been

watching Life's Biggest Questions - and until next time, you take it easy.

For more infomation >> What If Rodan Was Real? - Duration: 7:10.

-------------------------------------------

What is your Body Worth? The Ethics of Commodifying Human Tissues - Duration: 57:51.

[MUSIC PLAYING]

MARINA: William Kabasenche is the assistant professor

of philosophy at Washington State University.

He earned his PhD at the University of Tennessee.

And in addition to philosophy, he's

been a participating faculty member in the WSU Center

for Reproductive Biology.

He's the co-director of the ethics committee

of Pullman Regional Hospital and director of WSU Global Campus's

Bioethics Graduate Certificate, which

is online and course-based.

So he's just the best expert you could possibly

have for this topic.

WILLIAM KABASENCHE: We'll see.

MARINA: All right.

Well, we'll go ahead and get started.

WILLIAM KABASENCHE: All right, Marina.

Thank you very much for joining us tonight.

So let's see.

We'll skip the getting to know each other.

We actually know each other a little bit.

But here's a question that you can type an answer to, OK.

So how much is your body worth?

That's the title of the talk.

And well, before I say any more, why don't you answer with A,

B, C, or D. I assume you can see the slide.

Let us know if you can't see the slide that says

"how much is your body worth?"

And then, option A is $900,000.

Option B is $250,000.

Option C is $3 billion dollars.

And option D is priceless.

Marina says she can see the slide.

And she doesn't know.

Well, you've got to pick one of them.

And in different ways, more than one of these

could be a right answer.

So you actually have a decent chance

of getting a right answer.

[LAUGHS] "I think D."

OK, good.

That sounds like the kind of response

that you might hear a lot in an ethics course.

So in one context, I'll argue for D. I'll say you're right.

That's the right answer.

In another context, I'll show you

why C is actually the market value

at least for one particular person, whose case we'll

talk about.

And then, in a book that I read a few months ago

by Scott Carney called The Red Market-- actually,

is it The Red Market or The Blood Market?

I always forget.

Yeah, The Read Market.

Carney argues-- and I have a reference

later on in the presentation, so you'll be able to see that.

Carney argues that $250,000 is probably the

on average best answer, if you actually wanted

to give A, B, or C as your answer, and not D,

and say that your body is priceless.

And so, there's no price that can adequately

express its worth.

So Carney says $250,000 for the average,

typically for an American, who's generally in good health.

If, after you die, they were to sort of cut you up

and sell the parts--

[LAUGHS] sounds kind of gruesome when you say it that way--

$250,000 is what your family could

get for different body parts.

But as I said, we'll talk a bit about C.

And we'll also talk about D as potential answers

to this question.

So I want to look at three different sort of cases

and use each of them as a lens to think

about three different sorts of questions.

So the first question-- what's the value of your gametes?

This is an advertisement from an organization

up in Spokane, NW Cryobank.

And this organization has actually

been putting ads in the Daily Evergreen.

I haven't seen one in the past semester or two.

But before that, I saw them every semester,

starting when I came in the fall of 2007.

And there was no good way to copy the ad.

But basically, it talks about fulfilling

someone's lifelong dream by donating an egg.

And then, the rest of the text reads,

fulfill your lifelong dreams with the money we'll give you--

$16,000 we'll give you.

So we're going to talk a bit more about the prospect

of selling gametes, right.

Typically, this is called "egg donation."

In fact, you see it right there on the slide.

But it's not donation at all.

It's selling, right.

So a number of bioethicists argue

that it's better to call this "egg

vending" than "egg donation."

We'll talk a little bit about that case.

And this is another ad.

To show you the extremes that this can go,

this is an ad that was placed in the Stanford newspaper.

So williamn@alumni.stanford.edu is seeking a high-achiever egg

donor.

And another, similar ad-- an ad that was almost exactly like

this, in terms of asking basically for an egg from

an ideal student at Yale--

promised $50,000 to $100,000 for the right egg donor.

And so, this is a more recent ad, this one from Stanford.

But it's illustrating the same idea,

right-- that there's quite a market, as it turns out,

in the United States for selling eggs.

And so we'll talk more about how you

may determine the price of an egg, for instance.

So that's one case we're going to look at.

Another case is represented by these two images.

The gentleman on the left--

on my left-- with the goatee, his name is John Moore.

And the gentleman on the right in the lab coat is Dr.

David Golde, or "Gold-ee"--

I'm not sure how he says his name.

And I'll tell an interesting story about John Moore.

He's actually got an interesting genetic variation

that makes his tissues worth $3 billion on the market.

So that's where one of the answers in the multiple choice

came from.

And in the last case--

actually, this is the first case we'll

talk about-- but, if you've read this year's common reading

book, The Immortal Life of Henrietta

Lacks, then you might know a little bit about Henrietta's

story.

If not, I'll tell you a little bit about it.

And hopefully it will intrigue you.

And you'll be interested in going to read the book.

It's a really interesting read.

So we're look in more depth at that quote in just a second

and talk about some of the ethical issues related

to that, as well.

So three issues that I want to talk about tonight-- one

is informed consent, which, Marina,

I know you already know something

about because you've been in the biomedical ethics course.

The second issue is a set of issues,

really surrounding commercial value for human tissues.

And the specific question I want to think about,

with respect to commercially-valuable tissues

is, who has a right to the money that's

available to be made on these commercially-valuable tissues?

So that's the second sort of issue we'll talk about.

And then the third, I'm going to label it "expressive value."

In other words, we'll be thinking about questions like,

what does it say, what does it express about a person,

to say that you're willing to pay upwards of $100,000 for one

of her eggs--

for a set of her eggs?

And by contrast, what might it express

about the value of other people if you're not

willing to pay $100,000 for their eggs?

So those are the three ethical issues that I want to look at.

All of them are related to the idea of commodification.

And to commodify something is just to put it on a market--

to give it a kind of market value.

So for instance, when we go to the store

and we pay the market price for groceries at Safeway,

or for car at the car dealer, or for a new iPad, or something

like that, we're buying things on a market.

And all the objects that we buy and sell on a market

are commodities.

And so, when you put something on the market,

you're commodifying it.

That's where that term comes from.

So these are three different instances

of commodifying human tissues.

And there are obviously some interesting ethical questions,

I think, really to each one of them.

So we'll buzz in.

So Henrietta Lacks lived in the first part of the 20th century.

She was born in a time when segregation was still

very much a part of our country's history.

She grew up very poor.

It's almost hard to overstate how poor her family was.

She married a cousin of hers, which was actually not uncommon

during that time.

She grew up in Virginia.

And after marrying, she moved with her husband

to the Baltimore area where she spent most of her life.

There were more job opportunities

for both Henrietta and her husband in Baltimore.

And so she moved there.

And she became sick around the age of 30.

She started noticing some unusual symptoms.

And so she went to Johns Hopkins Hospital.

At that time, Johns Hopkins Hospital

was one of the few hospitals in the area, and even

in the country, that would offer free care to people

who couldn't otherwise afford health care.

And so, she went there because that

was the hospital that she could essentially afford to go to.

And when she went there, she was diagnosed with cervical cancer.

And so, the doctors tried a number of different treatments.

And among the things that happened

while she was being treated for cancer at Johns Hopkins,

was that the doctors--

including Dr. Gey, G-E-Y, who's mentioned in this quote--

Dr. Gey took some cells from Henrietta's cervix.

And, in the course of trying to figure out

how to treat her cancer, he made a pretty remarkable discovery.

And the discovery was that her cells were immortal,

to use the language that was being used

by the scientists at the time.

And what this means, basically, is

that her cells would replicate.

They would just continue dividing.

And they never died.

Actually, that's not completely accurate to say it like that.

Cells would die.

But before they did, the cells would divide

and so there was a continuous source of living cells.

And so, she's an unusual case in that respect

because, most of us, if you were to take a tissue

culture, a cell culture from us, the cells

would die after a while.

And so, what Henrietta's cells represented

was basically a huge new set of opportunities

for biomedical researchers.

They could now culture cells and use them

for all kinds of purposes.

And indeed, these cells were instrumental in the development

of the vaccine for polio, which was

killing many people through the middle of 20th century.

They were used to develop a whole host

of different vaccines for other killer diseases.

They were used in an almost infinite number

of science experiments that depended

on having a stable and consistent cell culture.

And in other words, the scientists

want to be able to control for things like the genetic makeup

of a cell.

Henrietta Lacks' cells-- these came to be referred to as "HeLa

cells"--

H-E-L-A, for the first two letters of her first and last

name.

And these HeLa cells, because they're all

genetically identical, because they all

come from the same individual, they

represent an opportunity to basically create

well-controlled conditions for doing experiments on cells.

And so basically, it's really not

overstating the case to say that Henrietta Lacks--

her cells revolutionized biomedicine

in the second half of the 20th century

and on into the 21st century.

In fact, although I've never actually talked

to a scientist about this specific question on campus,

I can say almost with certainty that there

are HeLa cells on WSU's campus.

And I say that just because they're

everywhere in the world-- literally, in the world.

And as it turns out, a lot of money

has been made off of them.

Unfortunately, Henrietta died shortly

after this cell culture was taken.

The doctors were not able to successfully treat her cancer.

So she passed away.

And her family thought that was the end of things.

They never knew that the cells had been taken.

And they never knew, up until about the mid-1970s,

well after her death--

a few decades after her death--

that these cells had any significance.

So in the intervening time, a number of companies

were started.

A number of people made a lot of money.

A whole bunch of people benefited

in a whole lot of ways.

And her own family didn't know this until a Rolling Stone

expose article in the mid-'70s.

And then, Rebecca Skloot's book, The Immortal Life

of Henrietta Lacks, sort of develops the story

in much, much more detail.

And she spent a lot of time with family members

and gets their perspective.

That's right, Rolling Stone, investigative journalism

at its best--

right next to an article on the latest pop star or something

like that.

So that brings us to this quote, right.

So Bobbette, who is one of Henrietta's daughters,

she says, "'You know what is a myth?

Everybody always saying Henrietta Lacks

donated those cells.

She didn't donate nothing.'" And Skloot tries to stick very

close to the actual manner of speaking in Henrietta's family.

So Bobbette is African-American, as was her mother.

"'She didn't donate nothing.

They took them and didn't ask.'

She inhaled a deep breath to calm herself.

'What would really upset Henrietta

is the fact that Dr. Gey never told the family anything.

We didn't know nothing about those cells and he

didn't care.'"

So this is pretty remarkable.

And the family was completely unaware of everything

that had been going on.

So there's a revolution going on in biomedicine.

And they are completely unaware of it.

People are making, as I've already emphasized,

money off of these cells.

Her family remains in poverty.

I mean, she has family members even today

who can't afford health care of their own.

And so, I mean, there's a kind of awkward tension

between, on the one hand, the fact that all of this benefit

has been gained--

and the other hand, the fact that Henrietta never

gave anything like informed consent

to the taking and the use of these cells, right.

So, this raises the question that, Marina,

I know you already appreciate the significance of.

Well, what's informed consent?

And why is it a fundamental ethical requirement

for both health care practice, which we have talked about,

and biomedical research, which we'll start talking

about on Friday of this week.

So that's a picture of the Nazi doctors on trial.

And the reason I put that picture in the presentation

is because it was when the world discovered in the mid-1940s

what the Nazi doctors had been doing.

Basically everybody reacted in horror.

The Nazi doctors had engaged in all kinds of experimentation.

They did horrible things-- graphically horrible things.

They would give people gunshot wounds or knife wounds,

and then basically see whether they healed on their own.

They would dunk people in cold water

or expose them too intensely high levels of radiation

to see how they recovered, or if they recovered.

They attempted to sew together genetically identical twins

to see if they could create a conjoined twin.

They had twins having sex with one another

to see if the offspring were healthy or in what ways

they weren't healthy.

All host of really horrific experiments.

And so, at the Nuremberg Trials, which

is where this picture was taken--

yeah, sheesh-- at the Nuremberg Trials,

a number of these doctors were convicted and actually

executed for the things that they did.

And one of the things that came out of that

was the Nuremberg Code.

And this code was basically a code of research ethics.

And the very first thing-- literally,

the first sentence of the code--

and this won't be a direct quote.

But this is essentially what it says-- researchers should never

do any research on experimental subjects

without getting their consent.

And so, if for no other reason, a researcher

should want to get informed consent just so that they don't

become, in effect, like the Nazi doctors

who basically ignored anything like informed consent

and did all kinds of horrible things to patients

without getting their consent in anything.

So there are two features of informed consent.

The first part is the informed part.

And that has to do with this question.

What information is material?

What information is relevant to your health care decisions?

To your life decisions?

To any decisions you might make to participate in research?

So for instance, we could ask in the context of the Henrietta

Lacks case, what kind of information

would Henrietta want to have had if she was going

to make a truly informed decision to, say, donate

her cells to biomedical research.

So what kind of information would you need to know?

That's sort of the first part of informed consent.

And basically, the way to answer that question

is to ask, maybe, what kind of information

would I want to know if I was going to be

a participant in this research?

Doesn't mean that the participant in research

has to understand everything that the researcher does.

But they have to understand enough to understand

the significance of the decision that they're making.

And then, the second part of informed consent

is the consent part.

And then so the question I pose here

is, under what conditions can you make

a decision that represents you?

That really reflects your identity and your values?

What you want to do with your life?

So, if someone coerces you, or if someone lies to you,

or if someone manipulates you, you made a decision, sort of.

But it's not really a decision that

is made under voluntary or consensual conditions.

And so, that doesn't have anything

like the kind of power of a decision

that you make where you are truly

free to make the decision that represents your values

and represents what you want to do with your life--

or your cells, if you're Henrietta Lacks.

So I like this little picture.

It says, "I think I voted."

I think that picture was created in the context of some

of the recent controversies in the United States

about whether votes were being properly counted.

But, Marina, you know that I used in class

the example of someone who covers her eyes,

and backs into a voting booth, and just

pulls a lever at random.

And in one sense, we say, well, yeah, that person voted.

But in another, more important sense,

I think it's more important we say they really didn't vote,

because that wasn't a meaningful act.

They didn't act with anything like an informed understanding

of what they were doing.

And so, informed consent, meaningful autonomy,

is about making decisions that really do reflect values,

really do reflect what you want to do, as opposed

to just sort of blindly choosing,

as someone would do if they backed into a voting booth

and called that their vote.

Not exactly a vote.

So among many other things that we

might learn from the Henrietta Lacks, case, one of them

is that biomedical researchers should be much, much

more careful about getting the informed

consent of any potential participants in research.

And in Henrietta Lack's case, this

means that, again, among many other things,

the researchers should have asked her,

can we take some of your cells--

not just to provide you with therapy for your cancer-- but

can we take cells that we hope to be able to use for research

purposes?

And additional questions might be, well, what kinds of things

are you willing to let us do with your cells?

So informed consent is one part of the ethics

of commodification.

Because if nothing else, the Henrietta Lacks story

tells us that people shouldn't get to take your bodily tissues

and use them without your knowledge,

without you being able to decide whether you

want to participate in that.

And that, of course, also leads us

into the next question, which is,

and maybe you should get to decide whether or not

you benefit from the use of your cells.

So let's move on now to a second case.

So as I said earlier, John Moore,

the gentleman with goatee on the left,

he got the leukemia unfortunately in the mid-1970s.

And so he went to a doctor at the UCLA Medical Center--

Dr. David Golde, who's the gentleman

on the right in the lab coat.

And in the course of treating Moore's leukemia,

Dr. Golde took a number of tissues

because he was trying to understand

the origin of the cancer.

And he was trying to figure out how

best to treat the cancer as it existed in Moore's body.

And so he took a whole bunch of tissues.

And eventually, he actually invited Moore to fly to LA.

Moore, actually, I'm pretty sure he lived in Washington state

at the time, maybe in the Vancouver area.

And so, he invited more to fly at least twice down to LA.

Moore was under the impression that he was flying down

for additional observation and treatment for his cancer.

But in reality, Golde was actually

taking additional tissue samples because he'd

made an important discovery.

Moore's cells contained a genetic variation that

basically led them to overproduce something

called lymphokimes, which are essentially

a booster for the immune system.

And so, Golde realized that he could make a lot of gold

with these cells.

He realized that if he could extract and purify

the lymphokimes, this particular protein,

he could create an immune booster that he

could sell in the market.

And I don't know if he was the original one

to make an estimate of the market value of if this was

done during the ensuing court case,

but eventually, it was determined

that the market value for Moore's tissues was $3 billion.

And so we've got two things going on in this case.

We've got one, the thing we've already

seen the Henrietta Lacks case.

Moore had no idea that he was participating

in biomedical research that was commercially valuable.

He just didn't know that.

He thought he was receiving treatment for cancer.

And he thought that was the only thing that was going on.

But now, a second question is, well,

who should benefit from the $3 billion

worth of lymphokimes that are in Moore's body

and then, eventually, in Golde's lab, as well.

Golde and some of his colleagues,

they made a patent claim on this particular set of tissues.

And when Moore found out what was going on

and realized that Golde and his colleagues

had patented his tissues and were already making

a decent amount of money off of it, he sued.

He brought a lawsuit.

And This lawsuit went all the way to a Supreme Court

in California.

And the Supreme Court made two separate rulings on the case.

On the one hand, they ruled in Moore's favor.

And they said Dr. Golde was guilty of malpractice,

which is to say, he misled Moore about why

he was bringing him in.

Moore thought it was for treatment.

In reality, it was for something else.

And so, the California Supreme Court

ruled that that counted as malpractice.

And so, Moore won an award from malpractice.

However-- and now, this is the real kicker--

the California Supreme Court ruled

in favor of Dr. Golde and UCLA because eventually the patents

were put in UCLA's name.

The California Supreme Court ruled

in Golde and UCLA's favor, saying

that Moore had no commercial interest in his tissues

once they left his body, right.

So in other words, once they were out of his body,

even in a context where he didn't know the precise reasons

why they were leaving his body, even still,

they argued he had no proprietary right.

He had no property claim.

Part of the lawsuit that Moore had brought was to say,

this is sort of like someone is stealing their property, right.

So if someone were to break into your house,

and steal some of your electronic equipment,

and then sell it on the black market or on Craigslist

or whatever, you could bring a claim against that person

and say, hey, this person benefited from my property.

They didn't have a right to sell what was my property.

If anyone has a right to benefit from the sale of that property,

it's me, because it's my property.

So that's the kind of claim that Moore was making.

And the California Supreme Court rejected that claim,

which is pretty remarkable.

That's crazy if you're observing.

So this raises, I mean, this question, right.

So who has the right to benefit from commercially-valuable

tissues?

And I want to say that there are three possible answers

to this kind of question.

The first answer, maybe the most obvious one,

right-- if you react like I initially do to the John Moore

case-- you think, well, if anybody should benefit,

it should be Moore himself.

After all, this came from his body.

These lymphokimes wouldn't exist if it were not for the fact

that Golde was taking them from Moore's body.

So he won a certain kind of genetic lottery,

Moore did, in that he was born, sadly,

with genes that would predispose him to have leukemia, but,

happily, in another perspective, with genes

that way makes his lymphokimes far more commercially

valuable than those in your body or mine, so far as I know.

And, so, one answer to the question

of who should benefit from these really valuable lymphokimes

is you say, well, John Moore should.

He's the one who was the donor of these tissues.

Now, I have a decent amount of sympathy

for that kind of answer.

It sounds right, in a certain way,

to say, yeah, if anybody is going to benefit,

it ought to be Moore.

After all, these are his bodily tissues.

And they were taken without his consent

and without his knowledge.

And that seems like a problem.

But on the other hand, if we think

about the kinds of things for which patents

or proprietary rights are given, those things

are usually entities where the person seeking

an intellectual property right, or a patent right, they've

made some sort of investment.

So for instance, if I write a book or an article--

or I just sent off an author permission document today

for an article I've written, and in that kind

of case, we would say that, well,

because it's my intellectual work,

I should be the one who retains a proprietary right to it.

And in this case, I was actually signing that right away,

giving it to the journal where the article's going

to be published.

But let's say that I write a book.

Let's say that I wrote the book, The Immortal

Life of Henrietta Lacks.

Well then, this is a bestseller.

It's a New York Times bestseller.

I should benefit from it in the sense

that the money that's there to be made on this particular book

should be money that I get.

And so, that's in a case where I've actually made

an intellectual contribution.

I've done something to make that book be of value.

And under those conditions, intellectual property law

is pretty clear that I ought to be the beneficiary.

After all, I've made the contribution.

But ironically, Moore didn't really do anything.

He didn't arrange to have this particular genetic

configuration.

He wasn't there telling his parents

which genes to give him.

And his parents actually had no control over it.

I mean, really, nobody had any control over the fact--

nobody made any intentional decision.

Nobody could take any responsibility

in any meaningful, intentional sort of way for Moore

ending up with these really valuable lymphokimes

in his body.

So it's a little funny to say that he should benefit,

because he didn't really do anything.

Now, you might say, well, he kind of won the lottery.

And I suppose there's something to that.

But in another sense, what he did or didn't do

is pretty different from what happens

when intellectual property rights are generally given.

And so, at that point, Dr. Golde might say, yeah, anyway,

I'm the one who did all the work here.

After all, I extracted these tissues.

I purified the gene sequence.

And I was able to start to collect these lymphokimes.

And so, I did all the work here.

And I should benefit, Golde might say.

So in other words, the second possible answer

is one that says, well, maybe the researchers should

be the one to benefit.

After all, they did the work.

Moore didn't really do any work.

All he did was be lucky enough to be

born with what turned out to be very

commercially-valuable tissues.

But he didn't do anything.

And he's certainly not responsible.

It's not like he wrote a book.

It's not like he did anything for which he should

claim intellectual property.

But the researchers can say that they did something.

And so, they could say, well, I think I have a good claim.

I think I have a right to benefit because, after all, I

did the work.

And I have some sympathy for that view, too.

But I think there's something odd about that view, as well.

And the oddness is this.

Golde could be a very, very competent--

indeed it seems like he is-- was-- a very competent

biomedical researcher.

But the fact of the matter is, is he could work a lifetime

and never gain the benefits that he actually did gain

from having run into and sort of stumbled upon Moore's tissues.

So in other words, although he's a skilled biomedical

researcher, the fact that he stumbled

onto these valuable tissues has nothing to do with his skill,

whatsoever.

He too, just like Moore, seems to have won the lottery,

in the sense that he just happened

to be in the right place at the right time.

And it's not clear that, just the fact that he stumbled

onto these valuable tissues means that he

should benefit from them.

In other words, his investment, the work that he did,

he could have done all through his life for other sorts

of reasons, and never happened to stumble on to tissues

that are worth $3 billion.

So there's something funny about giving him

the credit, because he just sort of got lucky.

Right, he could use all of his skills,

and nonetheless would have, in another context,

in another world, he never would have

run across Moore and his valuable tissues.

And so, all of his skills would never

have necessarily given him any particular commercial benefit.

So there's a third answer that, as I

thought about these issues, I kind of warmed up to.

What if we said that in those rare cases

where somebody has, like Henrietta Lacks or John

Moore, commercially-valuable tissues,

what if we said that nobody should benefit commercially

from the use of those tissues?

And in a sense, that means everybody

could benefit from the tissues in another sort of way.

Actually, I want to check to see what's coming in the next side,

so.

If we were to say that, we'd have a model for thinking

about commodifying human tissues that essentially said,

some kinds of things shouldn't be commodified.

So in a way, this is sort of like answer

D to the multiple-choice question

I posed at the beginning of the presentation.

Maybe nobody should benefit from these.

And if that were the case, then everybody

could benefit, in the sense that the cost of taking advantage

for patients of these tissues could perhaps be much lower.

And so, to think about this kind of option,

we can think about a not-for-profit model.

And the Mayo Clinics, as it turns out,

are the leaders in this area.

And Marina, you may recall, we talked about the Mayo Clinics

just briefly when we talked about access to health care

and health care costs.

So the Mayo Clinics are all not-for-profit organizations.

And so, what that means is, people who work there,

they make money.

They have a salary.

But it's not like there's a set of stockholders

who then make any additional profit that's

generated by the clinic.

If there's any additional profit generated,

it's actually returned to the patients,

or it's reinvested in improving equipment at the clinic.

So in other words, everybody makes the salary

that they signed the contract to make

at the beginning of the year.

But nobody makes an excess profit

on top of their original salary.

And so, what they do, is they provide us an example, right.

And they show us that health care can be provided

in a not-for-profit setting.

And as you may know, the Mayo Clinics

are very, very good at what they do.

They are among the best health care providers in the country.

And so, if someone were to try to say, well,

if you don't have the prospect of making a big profit,

you just won't be motivated to do a good job.

And I think the Mayo Clinics are sort

of a counter-example to that.

They show it's not necessarily the case.

The work that's done at the Mayo Clinics is top notch.

And nobody there is making a profit on top of the salary

that they signed a contract for originally, right.

And so, to my mind, this kind of corrects an odd imbalance

in the Lacks and Moore cases.

In both of these cases, on the one hand,

both Henrietta and John sort of got lucky

through no effort or no sort of contribution of their own.

They just happened to be carrying or possessing

these tissues in their body.

And on the other hand, as I've already pointed out,

the biomedical researchers who, literally, in both cases,

stumbled onto these tissues, it's

not as if the work that they did would have had any value

were it not for the fact that they actually

had these tissues.

So in other words, if we go back for a second

to this last slide, and we think about the first two answers--

the donor of the tissues or the researchers--

if there is a good case to be made for each of them,

maybe the way to break the tie is to say, neither of them

should get a benefit.

And this is what we could achieve

with a not-for-profit model, where

we say that nobody benefits.

When these kinds of issues are discovered,

they should be used in a not-for-profit context.

So for instance, if a corporation

is going to be created to disseminate

the benefits of HeLa cells or disseminate

the benefits of the lymphokimes in John Moore's body,

that should be a not-for-profit corporation, right.

Sometimes, I mean, again, to address the motivation

question, sometimes one of the arguments

in favor of creating property rights or intellectual patents

is to say that this will motivate researchers

to do biomedical research.

However, a counter-perspective goes like this.

It says, look, much research is justified by being

in the public interest.

And so, in many cases, what we want

is scientists who are committed to benefiting

the public as a whole, and not necessarily motivated just

to get rich themselves.

And there's another case that sort of illustrates

this a little bit.

So right now, the US Supreme Court--

the national Supreme Court--

is considering the case of Myriad Genetics, which

is a company in Utah.

And they discovered a pair of gene sequences

that are strongly correlated with breast and ovarian cancer.

And so, they placed a patent on those gene sequences

and the tests for them.

And that means that anybody who is going to take this gene

test to find out whether they have the genes that might

predispose them to breast cancer or ovarian cancer,

they have to pay a large sum of money.

And it goes directly to Myriad Genetics, the corporation.

And they make a lot of money off of this.

They're currently worth a few billion dollars

on the basis of these tests.

And so a group of scientists actually sued Myriad Genetics.

And the reason they sued was because they realized

that the fact that Myriad Genetics holds the patent

means that they were restricted from doing research

on this gene sequence.

And so, the scientists reasoned--

they've argue this way in court--

and this case has enough merit that it's gone all the way

to the Supreme Court.

They argued that they could maybe

create a more effective test.

They could maybe create a more efficient, less costly test

if they were allowed to do research

without having to pay huge amounts of money

to Myriad just to do research.

So in other words, these are scientists

who are claiming that they could do

what's sometimes referred to as "public interest science."

Rather than trying to make a lot of money off of it,

they would do it just in order to improve the test

and to improve health care delivery to patients.

And they're claiming in this lawsuit

that they're motivated to do so, that they don't need

to make the kind of profits that Myriad Genetics is currently

making in order to do this research.

And so, their lawsuit is basically a demonstration

of the fact that scientists can indeed be

motivated by public interest.

And they don't need to be motivated

by the prospect of making a huge profit

if they stumble onto a valuable human tissue or something

like that.

So this is kind of the case for a not-for-profit approach

to commercially-valuable tissues.

Rather than giving all the money to the donors, or all the money

to the researchers, or even attempting

to split the money between the two--

rather we should create not-for-profit organizations

that would disseminate the benefits

of this particular research, just like the Mayo Clinic does.

All right, so the last sort of case that I want to consider--

and, Marina, we'll actually talk about this in a bit more detail

in the course later on.

So you'll get to hear more about this.

But again, so there was an advertisement

in the WSU newspaper for a number of years.

And it states very clearly that a woman at WSU who's

responding to this ad could make up to $16,000

selling, vending, her eggs-- not donating them,

that's a misnomer I've already stated.

Selling her eggs.

So $16,000 kind of sounds like a good deal, right?

When I first came to WSU, and the first semester I

was teaching biomedical ethics, I was thinking about class.

And literally right before class--

because I had read other accounts elsewhere--

I started to wonder whether there

was any difference between the kind of money

you could make selling WSU eggs, or what

I've referred to as "Coug eggs," and the kind of money

that women at Stanford could make selling their eggs.

And as it turns out, there's an interesting disparity, right.

WSU eggs are worth up to $16,000.

Stanford eggs-- a similar ad, not the same company,

but essentially the same kind of ad--

Stanford eggs are worth $25,000 to do the very same thing.

So, this is to say that on the egg market,

there's a big difference-- $9,000 difference--

between WSU eggs, or Coug eggs, and Stanford eggs.

And you might think, well, what's the deal?

I mean, it's not like the women at Stanford

would be doing anything different from what I would

be doing as a WSU student.

How do you explain this difference?

So as it turns out, there's been a decent amount of research

that's been done.

And that research is showing that the leading determiner--

not the only determiner, but the leading determiner--

of the value of a woman's "donated" eggs--

really sold-- is basically her SAT score.

In other words, the higher your SAT

score, the more money you can get for your eggs

on the open market.

Now there's an irony.

I know, Marina, I see that you've typed

"nature versus nurture," right.

And so, you're right.

There's a huge irony in this.

As it turns out, geneticists now understand that DNA--

your genetic makeup-- contributes much less

than the typical person off street

might think to your actual intelligence,

to your actual SAT score.

A person who receives a modest genetic inheritance but studies

hard can score higher on an SAT or some other standardized test

than a person who got a great genetic inheritance but is

lazy and never used it, right.

So there are definitely both genetic and environmental

factors going on.

And the fact that people are willing to pay

more for Stanford eggs than Coug eggs, probably

reflects the fallacy of genetic determinism.

They've assumed, erroneously-- we know this--

that the genetics is going to determine

how intelligent the child would be that they

would have using this egg.

And so, there's an irony in the fact

that the whole practice is predicated

on overestimating the significance of genetics

and underestimating the significance of environment,

and parental upbringing, and all that kind of stuff.

But nonetheless, even with that error being noted ironically,

there is still the fact, which I think

is pretty interesting, that Stanford eggs, or the women who

donate their eggs, are perceived to be more

valuable in the market than WSU women and the eggs

that they might donate or vend, really.

And so this leads us to what I refer to

as the "ethics of perception."

OK, so you look at a person.

Here's Megan Fox.

Marina, this works a lot better with a more

male-dominated audience.

But there's Megan Fox from one of her movies.

I think it's in Transformers.

And if you hadn't already figured it out,

the first thought in most guys' minds

when they see that picture is not, oh cool, she's a mechanic.

In other words, when they perceive what's going on--

she's under the hood of a car.

And so, if it were a male under the hood of a car,

you might think, oh, he seems to know what he's doing.

He's fixing cars.

But that's not the first thing that most men

see when they look at a picture of Megan Fox like that, right.

They're not thinking, oh cool, she's a mechanic.

They're attracted to something else.

They're perceiving her in light--

I mean, in this case, it's a somewhat sexually provocative

picture.

She's got a lot of skin showing.

She's bent over in a way that is maybe enticing.

And she's got an alluring look on her face, right.

So what does the typical male see in that picture?

Well, they don't see, ooh, this is someone

who can help me fix my car.

They see a potential sexual partner or something like that.

And so, the question of, does it matter how I perceive you,

is sort of getting at these issues, right.

So many women are concerned about being objectified

in the way that Megan Fox is being

objectified in this picture.

I mean, I feel a little guilty even having the picture in.

But I think it makes the point pretty well that many people

are going to look at a picture like this

and immediately objectify her, make her a sex object.

They're not at all interested in her mechanical skills.

They don't care that she can fix that car.

All they care about is the prospect of having sex with her

or something like that.

And so, this is what I have in mind.

I mean, this is sort of an entree

into the ethics of perception.

So here's a quote.

Marina, you'll get to read this whole article

later on in the course.

But Elizabeth Anderson wrote an article called

"Is Women's Labor a Commodity?"

And she was thinking about surrogate motherhood, which

is where one woman will actually gestate and give birth

to a child, and then give that child up,

essentially for adoption, to another couple.

And so, in the context of thinking

about surrogate motherhood, she says this.

She says that "To say something is properly

regarded as a commodity--" Yes, Juno is a good example of this.

"To say that something is properly

regarded as a commodity is to claim

that the norms of the market are appropriate for regulating

production, exchange, and enjoyment."

So in other words, if I say if it's

proper to regarded cellphones or automobiles as commodities,

I'm saying that it's fine for the norms of the market

to regulate the production, exchange,

and enjoyment of those things.

But what about women's bodies?

Are they the sort of thing that should

be placed on the market in the way

that that picture from the previous slide

sort of invites the leering observer to do?

So, "The ideals which specify how

one should value certain things are

supported by a conception of human flourishing."

And then she says this.

This is the kicker line, right.

She says, "To fail to value things

appropriately is to embody in one's life

an inferior conception of human flourishing."

So in other words, what she's saying is,

is if you commodify things which should not be commodified,

this is going to undermine your ability

to flourish as a human being.

It's perfectly fine to commodify those things that

are appropriately placed on the market.

But if you try to commodify things that should not

be placed on the market, well, then you, in Anderson's view,

run into trouble.

Because she thinks that our flourishing depends

on perceiving people in the right sort of way

and relating to them and the right sort of way.

So if you relate to Megan Fox only in terms

of her sexual attractiveness, you kind of reduce her

to something considerably less than who and what she actually

is.

And so, there's a similar sort of concern

that could be going on when women attempt

to sell their eggs on the market,

and when those eggs have a different market value placed

on them, which is based on the perceived

value of the woman-- the intellectual value or whatever

of the woman who has donated the eggs.

And so, to real quickly sort of lay

of the terms of how this would go,

we have to distinguish between things that are instrumentally

valuable, right.

So here's my glove.

This is instrumentally valuable when it's cold out.

And I'm going to ride my bike home later tonight,

because it keeps my hands warm.

But a person is not instrumentally valuable.

In other words, the value of a person

is not just that they are useful to someone else.

Rather, a person has intrinsic value.

They're valuable in and of themselves.

And their value goes well beyond the fact

that other people might find value in them.

So however much you may value me as a biomedical ethics teacher,

if you do more than just value me instrumentally,

as you should, this would be to value me

as having intrinsic value.

So, to say that I have intrinsic value

is to say that my value goes beyond my value to you,

or my usefulness to you.

And that's kind of the concern that's at play here, right.

I mean, the worry is that when a woman is valued for her SAT

score or for the fact that she has

certain athletic or artistic abilities,

and those are what parents seeking an egg want,

in that context she's being valued instrumentally but not

intrinsically.

And again, to go back to Anderson,

"To fail to value something appropriately

is to embody in one's life an inferior conception

of human flourishing."

So when we make that distinction,

we can sort of get going on the train of thought that

suggests that the way to properly value people

is intrinsically.

And that means that we can't necessarily

place them on the market and say that they have value according

to their usefulness to us, as couples do when they say

that they're willing to pay more for Stanford eggs

than they are for WSU eggs, for Coug eggs, right.

And so, a libertarian would say, well,

you know, really, as long as there is consent involved,

anything-- anything-- can have market value, even people, even

sexual relationships.

So many libertarians, for instance,

would say that prostitution should be legal.

And they would try to argue that it's ethical

because they think, as long as it's consensual,

as long as the woman who's serving as a prostitute

gives consent, well then, there's

nothing wrong with this, right.

But if a libertarian really thinks about what it is about

relationships that makes them valuable-- so for instance,

if they really came to appreciate what a relationship

with intimacy is about, they would recognize that--

I forget it it's the Beatles or another old rock and roll band

that they have a song, "Can't Buy Me Love."

I'm sure it's the Beatles.

And then there was a movie made.

I think it was back in the '80s that this movie was made.

It's pretty cheesy today.

But the movie, Can't Buy Me Love,

really gets at just the issue, right.

If someone were to try to come up to you and say,

how much money do I have to pay you in order

for you to be my boyfriend or girlfriend or whatever?

They really don't understand the nature

of that kind of relationship.

If they think it's the sort of thing

that if you just pay a person enough money,

they could do it for you, right.

Because there's a huge difference between someone

who's just doing it for the money and someone who actually

does love and care about the person

they're in a relationship with.

And to the extent that libertarians think that those

kinds of relationships-- relationships of intimacy

and friendship--

are an important part of the world flourishing.

They have reason to care about expressive value.

They have reason to care about what it expresses

about another person if you say, I'm

willing to buy your services on the open market.

So I mean, that's a brief argument.

But it gives you a sense for why I

think even libertarians should care

about this issue of expressive value.

What is expressed by the way that we

value a person's gametes or other attributes

that they have?

And as I've already said-- and I kind of got ahead of myself

a little bit-- but our flourishing is, in large part,

dependent on having at least some

of these kinds of relationships.

And to the extent that that's the case,

we have reason to be concerned about practices

that fail to properly value people

for their intrinsic value, and instead try to give them

only an instrumental value.

So the test case here would be would

be the well-concealed sexist.

Imagine a person who is a sexist.

He thinks that women are inferior to men.

But he's also really tricky about it.

He never lets on that this is the case.

He never discloses his views, at least not among women.

So when he walks through life and looks at women,

he views them in sort of diminishing terms.

He looks at them as being inferior to him

because they're women.

Does it matter that he doesn't reveal this to the women

that he talks with and maybe even enters

into relationships with?

Well, I want to say, I think it does matter.

I think that the kind of relationship

that he could have with a woman, given his sexist perceptions

and his sexist views about women,

is very different from the kind of relationship

that a person could have who is happy to think of men and women

as being equal, as having equal moral status,

and not having any kind of sexist views

that sees women as inferior in one way or another to men.

And so, even a well-concealed sexist

will suffer for his failure to properly perceive

the value of the women around him.

So I mean, if the concern about expressive value

makes sense in a case like this, then it definitely

can make sense in some of these other cases.

And of course, the most obvious sort of case,

as I've already alluded to, is the gamete market.

And these eggs that are bought and sold on this market

are used typically in in vitro fertilization

or artificial insemination, and then

implantation into a surrogate mother, or something like that.

So people are actually trying to have children

using a practice that essentially reduces

the women who are the source of the eggs to their market value.

Which is to say, the women are reduced to the value

that they have as sources of intelligent children

in the future, or something like that.

Which is to say, that it seems like a practice

like this, from my perspective, fails to properly perceive

the value of the woman from whom the eggs come and also

expresses a sort of dismissive or diminished value

to these women, by suggesting that their value to the parents

or to the hopeful couple is according to what kind

of prospects they'll have for giving

the couple an intelligent child, or an athletic child,

or a child with blue eyes and brown hair

if that's what the couple is looking for.

All of these are the kinds of things

that couples can sometimes be seeking when they seek

to buy gametes on the market.

All right.

Actually, let me stop there.

There are a few other things we could talk about.

But, Marina, do you have any questions?

So I'm looking at the chat box.

And if you want to type anything in about any of the issues

that I've raised, we could do that.

So you're saying, not as of yet.

And then, I can just point to just a few other places

where commodification of human tissues is sort of going on.

So up until recently, there was actually an organization

right down on Main Street, in Pullman, called Bio-Medics.

And WSU students would pretty regularly go down there

to sell blood plasma.

So you may ask, well, what's that about?

Right.

And there are a few different issues.

Interestingly enough, there's a gentleman

who's an anthropologist named Richard Titmuss.

And he wrote a book, The Gift Exchange,

that's the name of the book.

And in this book, he argued that if people

sell things, like blood, or blood plasma,

or any other organs, he argued that this was actually

decreasing the safety of the organ market.

In fact, he showed--

he actually had evidence that when,

in the earlier part of the 20th century,

organizations started paying for blood donations,

the rate of hepatitis in the donor blood pool

actually went up.

So then it was, the blood pool became less safe

when it was on a market.

And so he argued, successfully, that there

should be laws in place that basically prohibited the sale

of any human tissue products.

And this was debated in Congress.

And eventually laws were passed that required

that organs be donated only.

That there could be no sale of an organ.

And so, there's kind of an odd juxtaposition, right.

I mean, now WSU students were going down and actually making

money donating-- again, the word "donor" is inappropriate here--

blood plasma.

And so, one attempts to explain the difference between laws

prohibiting the sale of blood and organs

and the law allowing the sale of blood plasma.

Because we could say that when the laws were passed,

some of the people who are creating laws

argue that since blood plasma is so readily renewed in the body,

that it doesn't make sense to think of this as having

anything like the kind of specialness

or the preciousness of organs.

And so, they tried to argue.

Now, I don't think that these arguments necessarily

get at what one of Titmuss's most important concerns, which

was actually that this is decreasing the safety.

When people are motivated by money,

they're willing to sell their blood or blood

plasma even if they know it's not safe, because they're

mostly out to make money.

Titmuss's argument-- the other part of his argument was,

if people donate these things, they

do so for altruist reasons.

They would have no reason to try to altruistically donate blood

if they knew their blood was dangerous,

so if they knew, for instance, that they had hepatitis.

But part of the justification is that blood plasma

renews quickly.

And the other part of the justification

is that the compensation is for the time and effort of giving

blood plasma, and not necessarily

for the value of the plasma itself.

And so, that was kind of part of the justification that was

given for making an exception.

I'm not so sure that that's a legitimate sort of argument.

I'm not sure if that really makes the case

that blood plasma should be treated differently

from other organs.

But I had some people ask these questions about why is it

that you can't sell organs, but you can sell blood plasma.

And so, I did some research.

And that's sort of roughly the story that I came up with.

OK, so I see that we've come up on 7:00.

So I feel like I should let you go.

Marina, again, I appreciate you participating.

And as I said earlier, if you want to ask more questions,

I'd be more than happy to talk with you.

I'm grateful for your interest.

For more infomation >> What is your Body Worth? The Ethics of Commodifying Human Tissues - Duration: 57:51.

-------------------------------------------

News24 - What one Man Utd star has done for staff is absolutely brilliant... what a gesture - Duration: 2:01.

 The left-back splashed out on 40 hampers worth more than £250 each from Knightsbridge store Harrods, according to the Mail

 Shaw then ensured they were given to staff who look after United's players throughout the season

 It's the second year in a row that Shaw has made a big gesture for hard-working employees behind-the-scenes at Manchester United

 **PREDICT FIVE RESULTS AND WIN £25,000 - FREE TO PLAY HERE** Last year he bought hampers from Fortnum & Mason but this time it was Harrods

 The Mail say his gesture unsurprisingly went down well when they were delivered last week

 On the pitch Shaw has been hailed for being far more adventurous going forward since Jose Mourinho was sacked

 Pundit Steve Nicol told ESPN: "Jose Mourinho restricts players. READ MORE: TWO REASON UNITED KNEW EXACTLY WHEN TO SACK JOSE  "It was funny, I was watching against Bournemouth and I saw Shaw, who is a left-back, running towards the opposition penalty box with two and three players behind him, in front of him, backing him up, looking for passes

 "You would never have seen that in a million years [under Mourinho]. "You would have seen Shaw stuck out on the left-hand side, running up a tramline

 "That's what he was told to do [by Mourinho]."

Không có nhận xét nào:

Đăng nhận xét